W.S.Armstrong.Moral.Scepticism, F I L O Z O F I A, ETYKA I METAETYKA, metaetyka, Armstrong, armstrong
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. , No. July ISSN – doi: . /j.- . . .x MODERATE CLASSY PYRRHONIAN MORAL SCEPTICISM B W S -A This précis summarizes my book ‘Moral Skepticisms’, with emphasis on my contrastivist analysis of justified moral belief and my Pyrrhonian moral scepticism based on meta-scepticism about relevance. This complex moral epistemology escapes a common paradox facing moral philosophers. I. A PARADOX Many moral philosophers today live a double life. They teach philosophy classes which study extreme positions, such as moral egoism, nihilism and relativism. Then they walk across campus to serve on ethics committees in hospitals or laboratories. This double life is filled with tensions. Suppose patient Bob tests positive for HIV, but his doctor Alice thinks that she should lie to her patient about the test results, because the bad news would hurt him, and doctors should do whatever is best for their patients. Alice goes to the hospital ethics com- mittee and asks whether it would be morally wrong for her to lie to her patient about the test results. It would be very unusual for any member of the committee to respond that morality is just an illusion, and so nothing is morally wrong. If such moral nihilism were expressed, it would be dismissed quickly with laughter or disdain and without argument. This reaction should be contrasted with that in a philosophy class which has studied moral nihilism, egoism and scepticism for a whole term. Many bright students have defended these positions in discussions. In her final paper, one student, Eve, argues that it is morally wrong for doctors to lie to their patients, but she does not even mention moral nihilism, egoism or scepticism. Eve would and should receive a low grade. A paradox arises when we enter moral epistemology and ask whether the committee’s moral belief and the student’s moral belief are epistemically justified. The hospital ethics committee seems justified in concluding that © The Author Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly Published by Blackwell Publishing, Garsington Road, Oxford , UK, and Main Street, Malden, , USA MODERATE CLASSY PYRRHONIAN MORAL SCEPTICISM the doctor should not lie, even though the committee never considers moral nihilism, egoism or scepticism. In contrast, the philosophy student does not seem justified in reaching the same conclusion, because she has no response to such extreme positions. This is paradoxical: if neither the philosophy student nor the committee can rule out moral nihilism, then how can this inability show that the philosophy student’s moral belief is not justified when the committee’s moral belief is justified? One main purpose of my book Moral Skepticisms (Oxford UP, ), was to resolve this paradox. The solution lies in contrast classes. II. CONTRAST CLASSES Contrast classes are apparent in explanations: temperature is the reason why it is raining as opposed to snowing, but humidity is the reason why it is raining as opposed to not precipitating at all. Similarly for reasons to act: my reason to bake my son a birthday cake on May as opposed to June is that his birthday is May , but my reason to bake him a birthday cake on as opposed to baking him a pie is his dislike of pie. When surveyed, all kinds of reasons seem to introduce relativity to contrast classes. Reasons for belief are no exception. Suppose I see a bird on my lawn and believe that it is a crow. I can distinguish my actual visual experience from the experience which I would have if the bird were a cardinal or an ostrich, but I cannot distinguish my visual experience from the experience that I would have if the bird were a raven or a rook. Hence my visual experience gives me evidence and a reason to believe that it is a crow as opposed to a cardinal or ostrich, but no evidence or reason to believe that it is a crow as opposed to a raven or rook. I am then justified out of one contrast class but not out of the other in believing that it is a crow. (Even a reliabilist should admit this, because a birdwatcher can be reliable at picking out some birds but not others.) The plausibility and usefulness of these relativized claims reveals a place for contrast classes in epistemology. This place can be specified by definitions: S is justified out of a contrast class c in believing a proposition p when and only when S is not able to rule out p and is able to rule out the disjunction of all other members of c . This account is analogous in some ways to conditional probability. Just as the conditional probability of p given q is calculated by counting only poss- ibilities where q is true, so we determine whether S is justified in believing p out of c by assuming that some member of c is true and then asking whether S has evidence against the alternatives to p within c . © The Author Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly May WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG This definition does not depend on any view about scepticism, so it should be acceptable to sceptics and anti-sceptics alike. Still, it illuminates scepticism when we distinguish two contrast classes: The extreme contrast class for a belief that p = all claims contrary to p , including sceptical scenarios which are systematically uneliminable The modest contrast class for a belief that p = all claims contrary to p which need to be eliminated in order to meet usual epistemic standards. To call certain standards ‘usual’ is not to endorse them but only to say that most people use them. In this non-normative sense, the usual epistemic standards do not require believers to eliminate sceptical scenarios, so the extreme and modest contrast classes di S is justified out of the extreme contrast class in believing p S is justified out of the modest contrast class in believing p . Judgements of this form are denied by two kinds of relativized moral scepticism: Scepticism about extremely justified belief = no belief is justified out of the extreme contrast class Scepticism about modestly justified belief = no belief is justified out of the modest contrast class. The former does not entail the latter, so a compromise is possible: Moderate scepticism about justified belief = scepticism about extremely justified belief but not about modestly justified belief. This compromise should be attractive to those who admit that we cannot rule out extreme sceptical scenarios, such as deceiving demons and brains in vats, but who also think that we can sometimes rule out all but one member of the class which needs to be considered in order to meet usual epistemic standards. III. MORAL CONTRAST CLASSES This structure applies neatly to moral beliefs. Just add ‘moral’ before ‘belief’ in the definitions. The only complication is that moral beliefs are relative to three kinds of contrast classes. A moral believer might be justified in believing that one act © The Author Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly er. These two contrast classes can be used to distinguish two epistemic judgements: ff MODERATE CLASSY PYRRHONIAN MORAL SCEPTICISM as opposed to a second act is morally wrong, without being justified in believing that the first act as opposed to some third act is morally wrong. Hence we need a class of contrasting acts . Similarly, a moral believer might be justified in believing that an act has one moral status (such as being morally right) as opposed to a second moral status (such as being morally wrong), without being justified in believing that the act has the first status as opposed to some third status (such as being supererogatory). Thus we need a class of contrasting moral statuses . Again, a moral believer might be justified in believing in one moral theory as opposed to a second moral theory, without being justified in believing in the first theory as opposed to some third theory (if, for example, he has a counter-example which refutes the second but not the third). So we need a class of contrasting moral theories . For any of these contrasts, moderate moral scepticism follows from these definitions if some moral believers can sometimes rule out all but one of the alternatives in the modest contrast class, but no moral believer can ever rule out all of the extreme alternatives lying outside the modest contrast class but inside the extreme contrast class. My book argues for this compromise. Although other extreme moral views could work, I focus on moral nihil- ism, which claims that nothing is morally wrong. It is important that real people really believe in moral nihilism on the basis of real arguments. Hence moral nihilism cannot be dismissed on grounds which some (such as Peirce) cite for dismissing general sceptical scenarios, such as deceiving demons and brains in vats, which nobody really believes in or argues for. But can moral believers rule out moral nihilism? No. To rule out a mem- ber of a contrast class, believers need some conflicting ground which does not beg the question. Some moral believers try to rule out moral nihilism by appealing to moral intuitions, but those moral intuitions are predicted and explained by moral nihilists with the help of biology and psychology, so it begs the question to cite moral intuitions against moral nihilism. Moral nihilism also cannot be ruled out by logic or semantics, because it is logically and semantically consistent when developed properly. Furthermore, no non- normative premises, inference to the best explanation, or contractualist framework can justify a denial of moral nihilism. To show all of this, I run through naturalism, normativism, intuitionism and coherentism in part II of my book. I cannot repeat those arguments here, so I shall simply take it for granted that we cannot rule out moral nihilism. It follows that we are not extremely justified as moral believers. None the less, in my closing chapter, I show how some of us can some- times use coherentist methods to rule out all but one of the alternatives in the modest moral contrast class. These methods are exemplified in properly structured ethics committees. The main philosophical trick involves © The Author Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG second-order beliefs about reliability. Again I cannot go into detail here, so I shall simply take it for granted that some moral believers are modestly justified. The result is moderate scepticism about justified moral belief. IV. RELEVANCE AND CONTEXTUALISM Everything I have said so far could be accepted by a wide variety of epistemologists, including invariantists and contextualists, because I have discussed only relativized epistemic judgements with explicit contrast classes. The classic disputes in epistemology arise over unrelativized epistemic judgements without explicit contrast classes. Some epistemologists might hold that unqualified epistemic judgements, such as ‘ S is justified in believing p ’, are primitive and should not be ana- lysed in terms of contrast classes at all. This dodge is hardly illuminating. Moreover, because so many epistemic judgements (and judgements about reasons of other kinds) are relative to contrast classes, the burden of proof seems to lie on anyone who claims that any epistemic judgements are excep- tions to that general pattern. Besides, almost any account of ‘ S is justified in believing p ’ will be equivalent to some account in terms of contrast classes. Thus there is no good reason to avoid contrast classes in the analysis of unqualified epistemic judgements. With contrast classes, several options arise, but I propose this analysis: S is justified (without qualification) in believing p = S is justified, out of the contrast class which is relevant, in believing p . This proposal should be obvious, since to call a contrast class ‘relevant’ here is just to say that a believer needs to be able to rule out all other alternatives in that contrast class in order to be justified without qualification in believing a member of that contrast class. What is at issue is relevance to the status of being epistemically justified, not relevance to practical purposes, to morality, to religion, or to anything other than epistemic justifiedness. This analysis is compatible with a variety of views about which contrast class is relevant. Invariantists hold that a certain contrast class is always relevant. Extreme invariantists see the extreme contrast class as always relevant. Modest invariantists see the modest contrast class as always relevant. Context- ualists then deny invariantism and hold instead that which contrast class is relevant varies from context to context. The standard version of contextual- ism claims that the modest contrast class is relevant in everyday contexts, and the extreme contrast class is not relevant in everyday contexts but is relevant in some philosophical contexts. © The Author Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ] |